The Might of the Pen: A Reputational Theory of Communication in International Disputes Author(s): Anne E. Sartori 笔的威力:国际争端中的传播声誉理论 作者:Anne E. Sartori
Source: International Organization, Vol. 56, No. 1 (Winter, 2002), pp. 121-149 资料来源资料来源:《国际组织》,第 56 卷,第 1 期(2002 年冬),第 121-149 页。
Published by: The MIT Press 出版商:麻省理工学院出版社麻省理工学院出版社
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3078672 稳定 URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3078672
Accessed: 26-02-2015 23:46 UTC 访问时间:26-02-2015 23:46 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. JSTOR 是一项非营利性服务,帮助学者、研究人员和学生发现、使用和利用值得信赖的数字档案中的各种内容。我们利用信息技术和工具提高工作效率,促进新形式的学术研究。有关 JSTOR 的更多信息,请联系 support@jstor.org。
The Might of the Pen: A Reputational Theory of Communication in International Disputes 笔的威力国际争端中的传播声誉理论
Anne E. Sartori
In fall 1950 the United States and the People’s Republic of China became embroiled in fighting that neither state may have wanted. President Truman sent UN forces, including U.S. troops, across the thirty-eighth parallel into North Korea. Prior to this action, Chinese leaders tried almost every diplomatic method available to communicate that China would enter the war if U.S. or UN forces crossed the parallel. On 30 September 1950, for example, Chinese foreign minister Chou En-lai publicly warned, “The Chinese people . . . will not supinely tolerate seeing their neighbors savagely invaded by the imperialists.” ^(1){ }^{1} U.S. leaders said they did not want to fight China, but they misread China’s myriad threats as bluffs and sent troops across the parallel. ^(2){ }^{2} China’s failure to communicate its resolve contributed to the ensuing tragedy. ^(3){ }^{3} Why did China’s communication fail? 1950年秋,美国和中华人民共和国卷入了一场两国都不希望发生的战争。杜鲁门总统派遣包括美军在内的联合国军越过北纬三十八度线进入朝鲜。在采取这一行动之前,中国领导人几乎尝试了所有可用的外交手段来表明,如果美军或联合国军越过北纬三十八度线,中国将参战。例如,1950 年 9 月 30 日,中国外交部长周恩来公开警告说:"中国人民......不会坐视邻国遭到帝国主义的野蛮侵略"。 ^(1){ }^{1} 美国领导人说他们不想与中国作战,但他们却把中国的无数威胁误读为虚张声势,并派兵越过了平行线。 ^(2){ }^{2} 中国未能传达自己的决心,导致了后来的悲剧。 ^(3){ }^{3} 为什么中国的沟通失败了?
The recent literature on crisis bargaining leads to a pessimistic conclusion about diplomacy: To convey information, threats must be costly, and verbal threats work only when leaders publicize them before domestic audiences that may remove them from office. ^(4){ }^{4} According to James Fearon, diplomacy is primarily a tool of democracies, not because authoritarian states do not want to use it, but because democracies are more likely to have the “audiences” that make diplomacy credible. ^(5){ }^{5} 最近关于危机谈判的文献得出了一个关于外交的悲观结论:为了传递信息,威胁必须付出高昂的代价,而口头威胁只有在领导人在国内受众面前公开时才会奏效,因为国内受众可能会将其赶下台。 ^(4){ }^{4} 詹姆斯-费伦(James Fearon)认为,外交主要是民主国家的工具,这并不是因为专制国家不想使用外交,而是因为民主国家更有可能拥有使外交可信的 "受众"。 ^(5){ }^{5}
I demonstrate formally that diplomacy works in the absence of domestic audiences. It works precisely because it is so valuable. When states are irresolute, they are tempted to bluff, but the possibility of acquiring a reputation for bluffing often deters a state from bluffing. A state that has a reputation for bluffing is less able to communicate and less likely to attain its goals. State leaders often speak honestly in order to maintain their ability to use diplomacy in future disputes. ^(6){ }^{6} They are more likely to concede less important issues and to have the issues they consider most important decided in their favor. The model thus suggests that in the (more complicated) real world, states use diplomacy to attain a mutually beneficial “trade” of issues over time. 我正式证明,在没有国内受众的情况下,外交也能发挥作用。外交之所以有效,正是因为它非常有价值。当国家举棋不定时,它们很想虚张声势,但因虚张声势而声名狼藉的可能性往往会使国家不敢虚张声势。一个国家如果因为虚张声势而声名狼藉,那么它的沟通能力和实现目标的可能性就会降低。国家领导人为了在未来的争端中保持使用外交手段的能力,往往会实话实说。 ^(6){ }^{6} 他们更有可能在不太重要的问题上让步,并在他们认为最重要的问题上做出有利于自己的决定。因此,该模型表明,在(更为复杂的)现实世界中,国家通过外交手段来实现问题的长期互利 "交易"。
States sometimes do bluff, of course. It is impossible to measure how often they do so because opponents and researchers may not discover that a successful deterrent threat was actually a successful bluff. Nevertheless, the model I present here has a theoretical implication about when bluffs will succeed: Diplomacy, whether it be honest or a bluff, is most likely to succeed when a state is most likely to be honest. A state is most likely to be honest when it has an honest reputation to lose, a reputation gained either by its having used diplomacy consistently in recent disputes or having successfully bluffed without others realizing its dishonesty. 当然,国家有时也会虚张声势。由于对手和研究人员可能不会发现一个成功的威慑威胁实际上是一个成功的虚张声势,因此无法衡量它们这样做的频率。尽管如此,我在此提出的模型对虚张声势何时会成功有理论意义:无论是诚实的外交还是虚张声势的外交,当一个国家最有可能诚实时,它就最有可能成功。一个国家最有可能诚实的时候是它有可能失去诚实的声誉,这种声誉要么是它在最近的争端中一贯使用外交手段而获得的,要么是它成功地虚张声势而没有让别人意识到它的不诚实而获得的。
Since a state that uses diplomacy honestly cannot be caught in a bluff, concessions to an adversary can be a wise policy. When a state considers an issue relatively unimportant and the truth is it is not prepared to fight, bluffing carries with it the possibility of success as well as the risk of decreased credibility in future disputes. The term appeasement has acquired a bad name, but not all states in all situations are deterrable. Many scholars believe that Hitler would have continued his onslaught regardless of Britain’s actions in response to Hitler’s activities in Czechoslovakia. ^(7){ }^{7} If Britain had tried to bluff over Czechoslovakia, its attempts to deter Germany’s attack on Poland would have been even less credible. Similarly, the United States’ acquiescence to the 1968 Soviet invasion of Czechoslovakia was not a high point of moral policymaking; however, given that any threats regarding Czechoslovakia would have been bluffs, honest acquiescence was the best way to preserve credibility. In the latter case, U.S. leaders seemed to realize the benefits of honesty; when Russian ambassador Anatoly Dobrynin told U.S. president Johnson that U.S. interests were not affected by the Soviet action in Czechoslovakia, “in response he was told that U.S. interests are involved in Berlin where we are committed to prevent the city being overrun by the Russians.” Johnson’s words reveal that he saw a difference between Czechoslovakia, where he was honestly admitting that there was no strong U.S. interest, and Berlin, where he was threatening and prepared to go to war. 由于一个诚实使用外交手段的国家不会被发现虚张声势,因此向对手让步可能是一项明智的政策。当一个国家认为某个问题相对不重要,而事实是它并不准备战斗时,虚张声势既有成功的可能,也有在未来争端中信誉下降的风险。绥靖主义一词已声名狼藉,但并非所有国家在所有情况下都具有威慑力。许多学者认为,无论英国针对希特勒在捷克斯洛伐克的活动采取何种行动,希特勒都会继续发动进攻。 ^(7){ }^{7} 如果英国试图在捷克斯洛伐克问题上虚张声势,那么它威慑德国进攻波兰的企图就更不可信了。同样,美国对1968年苏联入侵捷克斯洛伐克的默许并不是道义决策的制高点;然而,鉴于对捷克斯洛伐克的任何威胁都是虚张声势,诚实的默许是维护信誉的最佳方式。在后一种情况下,美国领导人似乎意识到了诚实的好处;当俄国大使阿纳托利-多勃雷宁告诉美国总统约翰逊,苏联在捷克斯洛伐克的行动并不影响美国的利益时,"作为回应,他被告知美国的利益涉及柏林,我们致力于防止柏林被俄国人占领"。"约翰逊的话表明,他看到了捷克斯洛伐克与柏林之间的区别,在捷克斯洛伐克,他诚实地承认美国没有强烈的利益,而在柏林,他则威胁并准备开战。
When states do use diplomatic threats to deter actions, they often succeed in persuading their challengers to back down. For example, the Anglo-Russian Treaty 当国家确实使用外交威胁来阻止行动时,它们往往能成功说服挑战者退让。例如,英俄条约
6. Jervis 1970,801970,80. 6.杰维斯 1970,801970,80 .
7. Rich 1973. 7.Rich 1973.
8. National Security Council 1968, 274. 8.国家安全委员会,1968 年,第 274 页。
of 1942 specified that both Britain and Russia were to withdraw their troops from Iran by March 1946. When the Soviets threatened to remain in parts of Iran, the U.S. chargé d’affaires in Moscow delivered a diplomatic note to the Soviet government calling for their withdrawal of troops from Iran, and the Soviet Union withdrew its troops. When Turkey threatened to invade Cyprus in June 1964, it was deterred by what its messenger called a “brutal note” from U.S. president Johnson. Johnson threatened to suspend military aid and to refuse to come to Turkey’s aid in the case of Soviet intervention if Turkey proceeded with its plans. ^(9){ }^{9} 1942年,美国与苏联签订了《1942年条约》,其中规定英国和俄国应在1946年3月之前从伊朗撤军。当苏联威胁要继续驻扎在伊朗部分地区时,美国驻莫斯科代办向苏联政府递交了一份外交照会,要求他们从伊朗撤军,苏联随即撤军。1964 年 6 月,当土耳其威胁入侵塞浦路斯时,美国总统约翰逊发出了一份被土耳其使者称为 "残酷的照会",吓退了土耳其。约翰逊威胁说,如果土耳其继续实施其计划,将暂停军事援助,并拒绝在苏联干预的情况下向土耳其提供援助。 ^(9){ }^{9}
The model I present here investigates the questions of why and when states can change each other’s minds about valuable information in international disputes using verbal threats to use force. The model I propose, unlike most other formal models of crisis behavior, examines states that are engaged in a series of disputes over time, potentially with different adversaries. The repeated game has an important advantage: States’ past behavior and concerns about future repercussions can influence both their present behavior and that of other states. Thus, for example, reputations are endogenous to my model, whereas in models of isolated disputes they are merely assumed. ^(10){ }^{10} In contrast to these others, my model implies that states’ behavior is entirely different when the defender has been caught bluffing in a recent dispute. For example, when a defender has recently been caught bluffing, its deterrence is less likely to succeed in the near future. 我在此提出的模型研究的问题是,在国际争端中,国家为何以及何时可以通过口头威胁使用武力来改变对方对有价值信息的看法。我提出的模型与其他大多数危机行为正式模型不同,它研究的是在一段时间内卷入一系列争端的国家,这些国家可能与不同的对手发生争端。重复博弈有一个重要优势:国家过去的行为和对未来影响的担忧会影响其当前的行为和其他国家的行为。因此,举例来说,在我的模型中,声誉是内生的,而在孤立争端的模型中,声誉只是假定的。 ^(10){ }^{10} 与其他模型不同的是,我的模型暗示,当防御方在最近的争端中被发现虚张声势时,国家的行为会完全不同。例如,当防御方最近被发现虚张声势时,其威慑在短期内成功的可能性就会降低。
The reputations for honesty and bluffing that form the core of my explanation differ substantively from the reputations for resolve that form a part of rationaldeterrence theory. Rational-deterrence scholars argue that resolve, or willingness to fight, is an enduring quality. They maintain that states can fight to acquire reputations for having resolve, and that possessing such a reputation enhances a state’s credibility in future disputes. ^(11){ }^{11} The reputations in my model are expectations based on past behavior about whether or not a state’s diplomacy will be honest in the immediate future. 构成我的解释核心的诚实和虚张声势的声誉与构成理性威慑理论一部分的决心的声誉有着实质性的不同。理性威慑学者认为,决心或战斗意愿是一种持久的品质。他们认为,国家可以通过战斗来获得有决心的声誉,而拥有这样的声誉可以提高国家在未来争端中的可信度。 ^(11){ }^{11} 在我的模型中,声誉是基于过去的行为而产生的对一个国家近期外交是否诚实的预期。
The article is organized as follows. In the first section, I introduce two ideas I use in my argument: “cheap talk” and common interests. In the second, I present the model. In the third, I show how reputations arise, demonstrate that even “cheap” 本文的结构如下。在第一节中,我介绍了我在论证中使用的两个观点:"廉价言论 "和共同利益。第二部分,我介绍了模型。在第三部分中,我将展示声誉是如何产生的,并证明即使是 "廉价 "的声誉也会产生 "共同利益"。
9. Under-Secretary of State Ball, in Lebow and Stein 1990, 362. While Lebow and Stein classify the Iran case as “not a deterrence encounter,” it was a situation in which the Soviets threatened and the United States issued a diplomatic protest in an effort to deter the threatened action. See Keesing’s Contemporary Archives 1946, 7757, 7865; and Herzig 1995. 9.副国务卿鲍尔,见 Lebow 和 Stein 1990 年,362 页。虽然 Lebow 和 Stein 将伊朗事件归类为 "非威慑性交锋",但这是苏联发出威胁,美国发出外交抗议以威慑威胁行动的情况。见 Keesing's Contemporary Archives 1946, 7757, 7865;以及 Herzig 1995。
10. For an example of a work that assumes the existence of a reputation by considering a single dispute in isolation, see Fearon 1992. For political science works that model reputations for resolve using multistage games, see Nalebuff 1991; Powell 1990; Morrow 1989; and Alt, Calvert, and Humes 1988. Huth and Leng also devote attention to the form in which past behavior affects the present. See Huth 1988; and Leng 1993. A large literature in economics also examines the formation of reputations, where reputation is usually tied to, but not perfectly correlated with, some enduring quality of the reputation holder. For an excellent review, see Wilson 1985. Following Axelrod 1984, regime theory has relied extensively on insights from the infinitely repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma. However, few works have created infinitely repeated games that are less stylized and more realistic representations of reality. 10.通过孤立考虑单个争端来假定声誉存在的著作实例,见 Fearon 1992。关于利用多阶段博弈建立解决声誉模型的政治学著作,见 Nalebuff 1991 年;Powell 1990 年;Morrow 1989 年;以及 Alt、Calvert 和 Humes 1988 年。Huth 和 Leng 也关注过去行为影响现在的形式。见 Huth 1988 年;Leng 1993 年。经济学中也有大量文献研究声誉的形成,声誉通常与声誉持有者的某些持久品质相关,但并非完全相关。有关精彩评论,请参见 Wilson 1985。继 1984 年的阿克塞尔罗德之后,制度理论广泛依赖于从无限重复的囚徒困境中得到的启示。然而,很少有著作能创造出不那么风格化、更真实地反映现实的无限重复博弈。
11. See, for example, Schelling 1966. 11.例如,参见 Schelling 1966。
diplomacy often changes an adversary’s mind about crucial information in a dispute, and discuss my concept of reputations and why war may be more likely in a world with diplomacy than in a hypothetical world without it. In the fourth, I revisit the Korean War case and argue that the model aids our understanding of this case. The model implies that deterrence is more likely to succeed if a state has not recently been caught bluffing; I argue that China’s threats to enter the Korean War were dismissed because they came in the context of called bluffs to fight over Taiwan. I conclude by summarizing the implications of this work and providing suggestions for further research. 外交往往会改变对手对争端中关键信息的看法,我还讨论了我的声誉概念,以及为什么在一个有外交的世界中战争的可能性要大于一个没有外交的假想世界。第四部分,我重温了朝鲜战争的案例,并认为该模型有助于我们理解这一案例。该模型暗示,如果一个国家最近没有被发现虚张声势,那么威慑就更有可能成功;我认为,中国加入朝鲜战争的威胁之所以被驳回,是因为它们是在虚张声势争夺台湾的背景下出现的。最后,我总结了这项研究的意义,并提出了进一步研究的建议。
Cheap Talk and Common Interests 低级趣味与共同利益
A growing literature on international crises argues that the existence of domestic audiences is the major source of diplomatic success. Drawing on a literature in economics that shows the effectiveness of costly signals, much of the recent international crisis literature argues that verbal diplomacy is costly. A costly signal is one that directly (and negatively) affects the sender’s payoff. For example, if one must pay $1,000\$ 1,000 to make a speech, that speech is a costly signal. ^(12){ }^{12} The audiencecost literature argues that domestic audiences “punish” leaders for backing down from a threat, and this punishment acts as a cost that makes diplomacy informative. ^(13){ }^{13} 越来越多关于国际危机的文献认为,国内受众的存在是外交成功的主要来源。经济学文献显示了代价高昂的信号的有效性,借鉴这一观点,近期的国际危机文献大多认为,口头外交是代价高昂的。代价高昂的信号是指直接(且负面)影响发送者回报的信号。例如,如果一个人必须付出 $1,000\$ 1,000 的代价才能发表演讲,那么这个演讲就是一个代价高昂的信号。 ^(12){ }^{12} 受众成本文献认为,国内受众会 "惩罚 "从威胁中退缩的领导人,而这种惩罚就像一种成本,使外交具有信息量。 ^(13){ }^{13}
This line of reasoning is problematic. If, on balance, backing down is best for a state, then most leaders and domestic audiences should support it. However, if war is best for the state, then most members of both categories should favor it. In neither case do domestic audiences as a group have any reason to punish leaders. ^(14){ }^{14} Although following through on a threat is sometimes a state’s best course of action, I show that backing down can be as well. Thus, contrary to the arguments of the audience-cost literature, rational audiences should not always penalize leaders for backing down. 这种推理是有问题的。如果权衡利弊,退让对国家最有利,那么大多数领导人和国内受众都应支持退让。然而,如果战争对国家最有利,那么这两类人中的大多数都应该支持战争。在这两种情况下,国内受众作为一个群体都没有理由惩罚领导人。 ^(14){ }^{14} 尽管有时贯彻威胁是国家的最佳做法,但我也证明了退缩也可能是国家的最佳做法。因此,与受众成本文献的论点相反,理性的受众不应该总是因为领导人退缩而对其进行惩罚。
Signals need not be costly to convey information to a listener. A second literature in economics has examined the effectiveness of “cheap talk” (costless) signals. ^(15){ }^{15} As Robert Gibbons observes, "The key feature of such a cheap-talk game is that the message has no direct effect on either the Sender’s or the Receiver’s payoff. The 向听者传递信息的信号不一定需要付出高昂的成本。经济学中的第二种文献研究了 "廉价谈话"(无成本)信号的有效性。 ^(15){ }^{15} 罗伯特-吉本斯(Robert Gibbons)指出:"这种廉价谈话博弈的主要特点是,信息对发送者或接收者的报酬都没有直接影响。这就是
only way the message can matter is through its informative content: by changing the Receiver’s belief about the Sender’s type, a message can change a Receiver’s action, and thus indirectly change both players’ payoffs." ^(16){ }^{16} 信息发挥作用的唯一途径是它的信息内容:通过改变接收者对发送者类型的信念,信息可以改变接收者的行动,从而间接地改变双方的收益"。 ^(16){ }^{16}
Diplomacy is the epitome of “cheap talk.” It includes speeches, conversations between state leaders, and diplomatic notes. Actions are part of the lexicon, ^(17){ }^{17} but often they are also “cheap” relative to the issue at stake in a dispute, such as protecting the independence of an ally, avoiding a war, or maintaining the illusion of military superiority. Any state would be willing to pay the small monetary costs of moving an aircraft carrier if doing so would decide a crisis in its favor. Thus, the monetary costs of diplomacy meet the technical requirement for successful costly signaling, but not the real-world test. 外交是 "廉价谈话 "的缩影。它包括演讲、国家领导人之间的对话和外交照会。行动也是外交词汇的一部分, ^(17){ }^{17} 但相对于争端中的利害关系而言,行动往往也是 "廉价 "的,例如保护盟友的独立、避免战争或维持军事优势的假象。任何国家都愿意为移动航母付出微薄的金钱成本,只要这样做能使危机朝着有利于自己的方向发展。因此,外交的货币成本符合成功发出高成本信号的技术要求,但不符合现实世界的检验标准。
How does one state convince another? A defender’s ability to convince a challenger stems from both its and its challenger’s behavior and expectations. A challenger will believe a defender’s threats only if the challenger expects the defender to be using diplomacy honestly; in other words, some honesty is a prerequisite for effective diplomacy. For diplomatic threats to make a difference, states that threaten must be more likely to fight than those that do not. 一个国家如何说服另一个国家?防御方说服挑战方的能力源于防御方及其挑战方的行为和期望。只有当挑战者期望防御者诚实地使用外交手段时,挑战者才会相信防御者的威胁;换句话说,一定程度的诚实是有效外交的先决条件。要使外交威胁发挥作用,威胁国必须比不威胁国更有可能参战。
The cheap-talk literature shows that communication through words and other costless signals is more likely when the speaker and the listener have interests in common. If two parties have the same goals, the speaker has an incentive to speak honestly and the listener has no reason to doubt the speaker’s information. For example, during the Persian Gulf War, the United States agreed to provide Israel with early warning of Iraqi missile launches against it. ^(18){ }^{18} The United States had an incentive to give truthful information because it wanted the Israelis to be able to defend themselves. Israel, in turn, had every reason to trust the information. 廉价言论的文献表明,当说话者和听话者有共同利益时,通过语言和其他无成本信号进行沟通的可能性更大。如果双方目标一致,说话者就有动力诚实地说话,听话者也就没有理由怀疑说话者的信息。例如,在波斯湾战争期间,美国同意向以色列提供伊拉克发射导弹的早期预警。 ^(18){ }^{18} 美国有提供真实信息的动机,因为它希望以色列人能够自卫。反过来,以色列也完全有理由相信这些信息。
When the listener may use the information to the speaker’s disadvantage, the speaker has an incentive to lie. Incentives to lie are stronger when states have divergent preferences. Again in the Gulf War, the Iraqis dramatically announced that coalition forces had hit a “baby milk” factory. The United States countered that only the part of the factory producing biological weapons had been hit. In this case, it is possible that each party was not being fully honest in an effort to manipulate the United States’ partners in the coalition. ^(19){ }^{19} 当听者可能利用信息对说者不利时,说者就有了说谎的动机。当各国的偏好不同时,说谎的动机就会更强。同样是在海湾战争中,伊拉克人戏剧性地宣布联军袭击了一家 "婴儿牛奶 "工厂。美国则反驳说,被击中的只是工厂生产生物武器的部分。在这种情况下,双方可能都没有完全说实话,目的是操纵美国在联军中的合作伙伴。 ^(19){ }^{19} .
Interests do not have to be perfectly aligned for communication to occur. When preferences are neither identical nor opposite, as is often the case in international disputes, some communication may still be possible. 利益不一定要完全一致才能进行沟通。当偏好既不完全相同也不完全相反时,如国际争端中经常出现的情况,仍有可能进行一些沟通。
The Model 模式
The model rests on five main assumptions: 该模型基于五个主要假设:
16. Gibbons 1992, 212 (italics in original). 16.Gibbons 1992, 212(斜体为原文所加)。
17. Jervis 1970. 17.杰维斯 1970 年。
18. Freedman and Karsh 1994. 18.Freedman and Karsh 1994.
19. Ibid., 319. 19.同上,第 319 页。
War is costly. The costs include lives lost and weaponry and other resources used. 战争代价高昂。代价包括失去的生命、使用的武器和其他资源。
Leaders care more about some issues than about others. States engage in disputes about different issues across time, and these are of varying importance. For example, leaders usually consider home territory more important than other territory; Vietnam was more important to the North Vietnamese than to the United States. As Thomas C. Schelling has argued, for this reason it usually is easier to establish credible deterrence than credible extended deterrence. ^(20){ }^{20} A state also may consider one ally more important than another. Sometimes, security issues may be most important; at other times, domestic politics may make symbolic or ideological issues primary. 与其他问题相比,领导人更关心某些问题。各国在不同时期会就不同的问题发生争端,而这些问题的重要性也各不相同。例如,领导人通常认为本国领土比其他领土更重要;越南对北越来说比对美国更重要。正如托马斯-C-谢林(Thomas C. Schelling)所言,由于这个原因,建立可信的威慑通常比建立可信的延伸威慑更容易。 ^(20){ }^{20} 一个国家也可能认为一个盟友比另一个盟友更重要。有时,安全问题可能最为重要;有时,国内政治可能使象征性或意识形态问题成为首要问题。
Leaders are unsure of the value other states place on the issues. In particular, at the start of a dispute states do not know each other’s value for the disputed issue well enough to know whether the adversary is prepared to fight. A state cannot precisely infer an adversary’s value for the issue from information gathered in previous disputes; even if the issues under contention in two disputes are similar, they are never the same. For example, the disputes in Europe over the Balkans prior to and at the start of World War I differed in a variety of ways. ^(21){ }^{21} Thus, in each dispute, an adversary must attempt to ascertain anew whether the state values the issue highly enough that it is prepared to fight. 领导人不确定其他国家对这些问题的评价。尤其是,在争端开始时,各国对彼此在争议问题上的价值并不了解,因此无法知道对手是否准备战斗。国家无法从以往争端中收集到的信息准确推断对手对问题的价值;即使两场争端中争论的问题相似,它们也绝不相同。例如,在第一次世界大战之前和战争开始时,欧洲关于巴尔干半岛的争端就有很多不同之处。 ^(21){ }^{21} 因此,在每一次争端中,对手都必须重新确定国家对问题的重视程度是否足以让它做好战斗准备。
States believe that some positive probability exists that they will still be engaging in international relations tomorrow. Tomorrow’s interaction need not be with the same allies or adversaries as today’s. 各国认为,它们明天仍将参与国际关系的可能性是存在的。明天的互动不一定是与今天相同的盟友或对手。
Each state interacts with many others over time, and tomorrow’s interaction is unlikely to be with the same state as today’s. ^(22){ }^{22} The assumption does not necessarily imply that every state interacts with every other, only that each state interacts with many others over time. The states in the model could represent any state, or, for example, the states in a particular region. 随着时间的推移,每个状态都会与许多其他状态相互作用,而明天的相互作用不太可能与今天的状态相同。 ^(22){ }^{22} 这一假设并不一定意味着每个国家都会与其他国家发生互动,而只是意味着每个国家都会随着时间的推移与其他许多国家发生互动。模型中的国家可以代表任何国家,也可以代表某个地区的国家。
This last assumption simplifies the analysis, but it is not necessary for the results. Without the assumption, the challenger and the defender in the model would represent the same two states engaging in disputes about different issues across time. In that case, the argument and the equilibrium proofs still hold. The model would then explain how reputations arise between two states and lead to effective diplomacy. ^(23){ }^{23} 最后一个假设简化了分析,但对结果并非必要。如果没有这个假设,模型中的挑战者和防御者将代表同样的两个国家,在不同的时间就不同的问题发生争端。在这种情况下,论证和均衡证明仍然成立。这样,模型就能解释两个国家之间的声誉是如何产生并导致有效外交的。 ^(23){ }^{23}
The literature on reputations for resolve questions whether reputations generalize. ^(24){ }^{24} Do states pay attention only to interactions that involve particular adversaries or regions, or do they take note of all interactions? For the reasons discussed earlier, the model here shows that any of these kinds of reputation is logically possible. 有关 "声誉决议 "的文献质疑声誉是否具有普遍性。 ^(24){ }^{24} 国家是只关注涉及特定对手或地区的互动,还是关注所有互动?由于前面讨论过的原因,这里的模型表明,任何一种声誉在逻辑上都是可能的。
The model describes a series of international interactions between states. In each interaction, both the use of diplomacy and the use of force are possible. The stage game, depicted in Figure 1, represents a one-period interaction between a randomly chosen “challenger” and a randomly chosen “defender.” Many deterrence models, purely verbal and formal, share a similar form. ^(25){ }^{25} The repeated game consists of an infinite number of repetitions of the stage game-that is, in each period, each state believes there is a positive probability that it will interact with some other state tomorrow. 该模型描述了一系列国家间的国际互动。在每次互动中,都有可能使用外交手段和武力。图 1 所示的阶段博弈代表了一个随机选择的 "挑战者 "和一个随机选择的 "防御者 "之间一个周期的互动。许多威慑模型,无论是纯粹的口头模型还是形式模型,都有类似的形式。 ^(25){ }^{25} 重复博弈由阶段博弈的无限次重复组成,也就是说,在每个阶段,每个国家都认为明天它将与另一个国家发生互动的概率为正。
At the beginning of each period, a challenger meets a defender. Each is drawn from a pool of potential challengers or defenders. At the start of the stage game, the defender is in possession of the territory or other disputed issue. Each interaction may or may not become a dispute, then a crisis, then a war. At the beginning of the interaction, each state knows the other’s relevant history; it is aware of any speeches made and of all actions in its opponent’s previous two disputes.
At the beginning of a new dispute, each player “receives” a new value for the issue at stake. This value is the realization of a random variable uniformly distributed between zero and 1.^(26)1 .{ }^{26} Each state knows how important it considers this issue, but it does not know its adversary’s value for the issue; it knows only that its opponent has a value equally likely to be anywhere between zero and 1. The challenger’s issue value in this time period is i_(t)^(c)i_{t}^{c}, and the defender’s is i_(t)^(d).^(27)Ai_{t}^{d} .{ }^{27} \mathrm{~A} state’s valuation of an issue is its “type.”
Each interaction begins with a “talk” stage. In the stage game in Figure 1, the challenger moves first, deciding whether or not to turn the interaction into a crisis. The interaction becomes a dispute if the challenger makes a speech threatening to attack the defender if the defender does not resolve some issues in the challenger’s favor. If the challenger does not threaten, the game ends with the status quo maintained, and each state receives a one-period payoff of zero. If the challenger
pp : Probability of challenger’s winning if war occurs. pp :如果发生战争,挑战者获胜的概率。
T: Cost of fighting, which both states pay in case of war. T:战争费用,战争时两国都要支付。 i_(t)^(c),i_(t)^(d)i_{t}^{c}, i_{t}^{d} : Challenger’s and defender’s values for the territory or other issue in this iteration, respectively. The defender loses its value for the issue if it gives up through acquiescence, war, or backing down. In case of war, its expected value is p^(**)(-i_(t)^(d))-Tp^{*}\left(-i_{t}^{d}\right)-T. i_(t)^(c),i_(t)^(d)i_{t}^{c}, i_{t}^{d} :挑战方和防守方在本次迭代中对领土或其他问题的价值。如果防御方通过默许、战争或退让等方式放弃,则会失去其在该问题上的价值。在战争的情况下,其期望值为 p^(**)(-i_(t)^(d))-Tp^{*}\left(-i_{t}^{d}\right)-T 。
FIGURE 1. The stage game 图 1.舞台游戏
does threaten, the defender responds with its own speech; it says either that it “will defend” or that it “won’t defend” if an attack occurs. If the defender says “won’t defend,” it acquiesces to the challenger’s demands and gives up the issue. 如果挑战者发出威胁,防御者就会以自己的言论做出回应;如果攻击发生,防御者要么说 "会防御",要么说 "不会防御"。如果防御方说 "不会防御",它就默认了挑战方的要求,放弃了这个问题。
The challenger then may attack. If it does not do so, the status quo is maintained, and each player has a one-period payoff of zero. If the challenger attacks and the defender resists, war occurs. The challenger has a predetermined probability of winning ( pp ); the probability of winning is a function of the balance of forces 挑战者随后可以进攻。如果挑战者不进攻,则维持现状,每个玩家的单期收益为零。如果挑战者进攻,而防守者抵抗,战争就会发生。挑战者有一个预先确定的获胜概率( pp );获胜概率是力量平衡的函数
between the two states. ^(28){ }^{28} If the challenger wins, it acquires the issue (adding i_(t)^(c)i_{t}^{c} to its payoff) and the defender loses it (subtracting i_(t)^(d)i_{t}^{d} ). If the defender wins, which occurs with probability (1-p)(1-p), then the status quo is maintained and both players receive a payoff of zero. No matter which player wins, both pay the costs of war (subtracting TT from their payoffs). Thus, the challenger’s one-period expected payoff from war is (p^(**)(i_(t)^(c))+(1-p)**0-T)\left(p^{*}\left(i_{t}^{c}\right)+(1-p) * 0-T\right), and the defender’s one-period expected payoff is (p^(**)(-i_(t)^(d))+(1-p)^(**)0-T)\left(p^{*}\left(-i_{t}^{d}\right)+(1-p)^{*} 0-T\right). If the defender backs down, the issue is resolved in the challenger’s favor without war. The challenger gets a one-period expected payoff of i_(t)^(c)i_{t}^{c}, and the defender gets a one-period payoff of -i_(t)^(d)-i_{t}^{d}. (For simplicity, the model assumes that an attack with no defense amounts to the defender giving up the issue.) As in Gibbons’ definition of a cheap-talk game, a message in this game has no direct effect on payoffs. 之间。 ^(28){ }^{28} 如果挑战者获胜,它将获得问题(在其报酬中加上 i_(t)^(c)i_{t}^{c} ),而防御者将失去问题(减去 i_(t)^(d)i_{t}^{d} )。如果防守方获胜(发生概率为 (1-p)(1-p) ),则维持现状,双方的回报都为零。无论哪一方获胜,双方都要支付战争成本(从他们的报酬中减去 TT )。因此,挑战方从战争中获得的单期预期收益是 (p^(**)(i_(t)^(c))+(1-p)**0-T)\left(p^{*}\left(i_{t}^{c}\right)+(1-p) * 0-T\right) ,而防守方的单期预期收益是 (p^(**)(-i_(t)^(d))+(1-p)^(**)0-T)\left(p^{*}\left(-i_{t}^{d}\right)+(1-p)^{*} 0-T\right) 。如果防御方退让,问题就会以对挑战方有利的方式解决,而不会发生战争。挑战者的单期预期报酬为 i_(t)^(c)i_{t}^{c} ,防御者的单期报酬为 -i_(t)^(d)-i_{t}^{d} 。(为简单起见,模型假定进攻而不防御等于防御者放弃问题)。正如吉本斯对廉价言语博弈所下的定义一样,这个博弈中的信息对报酬没有直接影响。
When this interaction is over, each state begins another. Note that the state’s type does not persist from one dispute to the next. At the beginning of time (t+1)(t+1), the state will interact with a new potential adversary and the issue at stake will be different. 互动结束后,每个状态开始新的互动。请注意,国家的类型不会从一个争端持续到下一个争端。在 (t+1)(t+1) 时间开始时,国家将与新的潜在对手互动,所涉及的问题也将不同。
Effective Diplomacy 有效外交
The assumptions of the model suggest that even states involved in disputes have common interests. While each state prefers to have all issues go its way, in practice such one-sidedness is usually impossible. Each state has a particular interest in obtaining a favorable resolution of disputes about issues it considers the most important. Since the outcome of war is uncertain, a state is better off if it achieves deterrence success more frequently when it considers the issues more important. A state that considers an issue crucial sometimes finds itself interacting with another that cares much less about it. But the second state will someday find itself in a similar situation: considering an issue extremely important and facing an opponent that does not. All states can be better off over time if they are more likely to concede when issues are relatively unimportant to them and to resist on issues they consider relatively important. This process is a type of “trade” of issues over time. 该模型的假设表明,即使是卷入争端的国家也有共同利益。虽然每个国家都希望所有问题都能按自己的意愿解决,但在实践中,这种片面性通常是不可能的。每个国家都有自己的特殊利益,即在其认为最重要的问题上获得有利的争端解决。由于战争的结果是不确定的,如果一个国家在其认为更重要的问题上更频繁地取得威慑成功,那么它就会更有利。一个认为某个问题至关重要的国家有时会发现自己在与另一个对该问题不那么关心的国家交往。但是,第二个国家有一天也会发现自己处于类似的境地:认为某个问题极其重要,而对手却不这么认为。随着时间的推移,如果所有国家都能在自己认为相对不重要的问题上更倾向于让步,而在自己认为相对重要的问题上更倾向于抵制,那么它们的处境就会越来越好。随着时间的推移,这一过程就是一种问题 "交易"。
As I show formally later, states’ communications often are effective because of a communications “norm,” or entrenched pattern of behavior. When states act according to the norm, they acquire or assign a reputation for bluffing or for honesty. States disregard the pronouncements made by other states that have bluffed recently and been caught. Since they have no “honest” reputation to lose, states that have been caught bluffing recently try deterrence, whether or not they intend to back down. Since states benefit from diplomacy as long as others are listening, the 正如我在后面正式指出的,国家的沟通之所以有效,往往是因为有一种沟通 "规范 "或根深蒂固的行为模式。当国家按照这一规范行事时,它们就会获得或被赋予虚张声势或诚实的声誉。如果其他国家最近虚张声势并被抓住了把柄,那么这些国家就会无视它们的声明。由于没有 "诚实 "的声誉可言,最近被发现虚张声势的国家无论是否打算退让,都会尝试威慑。只要别人在听,国家就能从外交中获益。
possibility of acquiring a reputation for bluffing provides an incentive for states to use diplomacy honestly. 因为虚张声势而声名狼藉的可能性会激励各国诚实地使用外交手段。
The Equilibrium 平衡
Finding a logical outcome of this situation amounts to finding an equilibrium of the model. Like all infinitely repeated games, this one has many equilibria. ^(29){ }^{29} I characterize a perfect Bayesian equilibrium (PBE) that corresponds to my substantive argument. PBE is a solution concept for games, like this one, in which some players have information others lack. In a PBE, players update their beliefs rationally, according to Bayes’s rule, whenever Bayes’s rule applies. I use the technique of factorization, which allows one to characterize equilibria of infinitely repeated games. ^(30){ }^{30} Equilibria characterized using factorization involve credible threats and promises. The equations that characterize the equilibrium are presented in the appendix. ^(31){ }^{31} 找到这种情况的合理结果,就等于找到了模型的均衡点。与所有无限重复的博弈一样,这个博弈也有许多均衡点。 ^(29){ }^{29} 我描述了一个完全贝叶斯均衡(PBE)的特征,它与我的实质性论证相对应。完美贝叶斯均衡是一个解决博弈的概念,就像这个博弈一样,其中一些博弈者拥有其他人所缺乏的信息。在 PBE 中,只要贝叶斯规则适用,博弈者就会根据贝叶斯规则理性地更新他们的信念。我使用了因式分解技术,它可以描述无限重复博弈的均衡状态。 ^(30){ }^{30} 使用因式分解法描述的均衡涉及可信的威胁和承诺。表征均衡的方程见附录。 ^(31){ }^{31}
Disputes are rarely isolated events, and threats often do convey information. To show formally that cheap-talk diplomacy can be effective, I characterize an equilibrium in which the defender’s threats often convey information to the challenger about the defender’s value for the issue at stake. In the equilibrium I study, there are two sets of strategies: one in which the defender has a reputation for honesty and can partially communicate, and one in which it has a reputation for bluffing and cannot. ^(32){ }^{32} 争端很少是孤立的事件,威胁往往会传递信息。为了正式证明低声下气外交是有效的,我描述了一种均衡,在这种均衡中,防御方的威胁经常会向挑战方传递防御方对所涉问题的价值的信息。在我研究的均衡中,有两组策略:一组是防守方以诚实著称,可以进行部分沟通;另一组是防守方以虚张声势著称,不能进行部分沟通。 ^(32){ }^{32}
I define two concepts: A defender may bluff successfully or it may be caught. In the game, a defender “bluffs” if it says that it “will defend” without intending to follow through if the challenger attacks. A defender is caught bluffing in period tt if (1) the defender has begun the dispute with a reputation for honesty (the challenger is listening), (2) the defender says that it “will defend,” (3) the challenger attacks, and (4) the defender does not follow through. In Figure 1, then, the defender is caught bluffing in period tt if the outcome in that period is outcome 6 and if the defender began that period with a reputation for honesty. In equilibrium, defenders are more likely to bluff, and challengers punish the defender by not listening for two periods after a defender has been caught bluffing. 我定义了两个概念:防守方可能虚张声势成功,也可能被抓住把柄。在博弈中,如果防守方说它 "会防守",但不打算在挑战方进攻时继续防守,那么它就是 "虚张声势"。在 tt 期中,如果出现以下情况,防守方就会被发现虚张声势:(1) 防守方在争端开始时就以诚实著称(挑战方在倾听);(2) 防守方表示 "将进行防守";(3) 挑战方发动攻击;(4) 防守方没有采取后续行动。因此,在图 1 中,如果 tt 阶段的结果是结果 6,并且防守方在该阶段开始时享有诚实的声誉,那么防守方在该阶段被发现虚张声势。在均衡状态下,防守者更有可能虚张声势,而挑战者则会在防守者被发现虚张声势后的两期内不听防守者的话,以此来惩罚防守者。
While the duration of the reputation for bluffing-two periods-is chosen for mathematical convenience, a reputation is relatively short-lived for substantive reasons. ^(33){ }^{33} Not all possible durations of reputations, or “punishments,” make sense. On the one hand, for a reputation to exist, it must last for at least one period. On the other hand, it is implausible that the reputation would last forever; a reputation that lasted forever would correspond to a story in which a state caught bluffing could never use diplomacy again. In practice, a state does not lose its credibility for all time if it bluffs unsuccessfully once. For example, even after the Soviet Union backed down in the Cuban Missile Crisis, it did not abandon diplomacy thereafter. Thus, a plausible punishment lasts for at least one period but not forever. 虽然选择虚张声势的声誉的持续时间--两个时段--是为了数学上的方便,但声誉的持续时间相对较短是有实质性原因的。 ^(33){ }^{33} 并非所有可能的声誉或 "惩罚 "的持续时间都有意义。一方面,声誉的存在必须至少持续一个时期。另一方面,声誉永远持续下去是不可能的;如果声誉永远持续下去,就相当于一个国家被发现虚张声势,就再也不能使用外交手段了。实际上,一个国家并不会因为一次虚张声势失败而永远失去信誉。例如,即使苏联在古巴导弹危机中退缩,此后也没有放弃外交。因此,看似合理的惩罚至少会持续一段时间,而不是永远。
In the part of the equilibrium in which the defender has a reputation for honesty, its diplomacy is partially effective. The defender often tells the truth, and so its diplomacy convinces the challenger that it is more likely to fight than the challenger had previously thought to be the case (though it does not convey to the challenger its precise value for the issue). Thus, the defender sometimes can succeed in deterring attacks, either honestly or by bluffing. However, a defender that bluffs may be caught-that is, the challenger may attack. By reducing the effectiveness of a state’s diplomacy in the immediate future, a reputation for bluffing harms the state’s ability to deter attacks, including its ability to bluff successfully. Thus, when the defender has a reputation for honesty, it bluffs only when the temptation to do so is very strong. ^(34){ }^{34} The challenger listens to the defender’s diplomacy because it wants to know whether or not its adversary will fight. Since the defender often is honest, the challenger can learn something from the defender’s threats. 在均衡的一部分中,防守方以诚实著称,其外交手段部分有效。防守方经常说实话,因此它的外交手段让挑战者相信,它比挑战者之前认为的更有可能进行战斗(尽管它并没有向挑战者传达它在这个问题上的确切价值)。因此,防御方有时可以通过诚实或虚张声势来成功阻止攻击。然而,虚张声势的防御者可能会被抓住--也就是说,挑战者可能会发动攻击。虚张声势的名声会降低一个国家近期外交活动的有效性,从而损害国家威慑攻击的能力,包括成功虚张声势的能力。因此,当守方以诚实著称时,它只有在受到非常强烈的诱惑时才会虚张声势。 ^(34){ }^{34} 挑战者倾听防御者的外交辞令,因为它想知道对手是否会参战。由于防御方通常是诚实的,因此挑战方可以从防御方的威胁中学到一些东西。
In the part of the equilibrium in which the defender has a reputation for bluffing (the punishment phase), its diplomacy is ineffective. In this situation, the defender cannot lose a reputation for honesty, because it has none. Thus, it has every incentive to bluff. Because of its desire to avoid being duped, the challenger does not pay attention to the defender’s diplomacy. Under these circumstances, the defender bluffs more often, but its threats (bluffs or truthful statements) are less credible. 在均衡的一部分,即防守方因虚张声势而声名狼藉的阶段(惩罚阶段),防守方的外交手段是无效的。在这种情况下,防守方不会失去诚实的声誉,因为它没有诚实的声誉。因此,它完全有动机虚张声势。由于挑战者希望避免上当受骗,所以并不关注防御者的外交策略。在这种情况下,防御方虚张声势的次数更多,但其威胁(虚张声势或真实陈述)的可信度却更低。
Note that the “punishments” in this equilibrium are substantively sensible, unlike the common punishment schemes in infinitely repeated games. In my equilibrium, states “punish” those that are caught bluffing by refusing to listen; this makes sense because states that have been caught bluffing are less likely to be conveying information. (In technical terms, they are “babbling.”) In many equilibria of infinitely repeated games, the states doing the punishing punish only in order to 请注意,这个均衡中的 "惩罚 "在实质上是合理的,与无限重复博弈中常见的惩罚方案不同。在我的均衡中,国家通过拒绝倾听来 "惩罚 "那些被发现虚张声势的国家;这是有道理的,因为被发现虚张声势的国家不太可能传递信息(用专业术语来说,就是 "胡言乱语")。(在许多无限重复博弈的均衡中,进行惩罚的国家惩罚的目的只是为了
avoid being punished themselves. The states that must punish them, in turn, will do so only because they will be punished if they fail to punish, and so on.
The transition from the noncommunicative part of the equilibrium back to the communicative part represents the fading of a reputation. As time passes, the defender regains its reputation and its incentive to use diplomacy honestly. Why should reputations fade? Empirically, as discussed earlier, one observes that they do. Theoretically, the fading of a reputation represents behavior that is optimal in the circular way that all equilibrium behavior is optimal. As long as the challenger believes that the defender will drop its bluffing behavior, it is in the challenger’s interest to assign the defender a reputation for honesty. As long as the defender is likely to be honest, the challenger listens because it wants to know whether or not the defender will fight. However, as long as the challenger is willing to listen, it is in the defender’s interest to use diplomacy honestly because the defender is more likely to attain its goals with communication. Thus, as long as the challenger is listening, the defender makes listening worth the challenger’s time.
Figure 2 shows the equilibrium strategies more formally. If the defender was not caught bluffing in time t-1t-1 or t-2t-2, both states play the strategies in the top half of Figure 2; if the defender was caught bluffing, both states play the strategies shown in the bottom half of Figure 2. Recall that the values of the possible issues are scaled to be between zero and 1; the horizontal lines in Figure 2 represent the possible values of issues that could arise. A state whose issue value in the given dispute is in the specified range (for example, between zero and ll ) plays the strategy shown above that range. For example, if the defender can communicate, the challenger is deterred (it challenges, but it attacks only if the defender does not try deterrence) if it considers the issue at stake to be worth less than j^(35)j{ }^{35} Figure 2 presents both the generic equilibrium, in which the thresholds for switching strategies are represented by letters (j,l,m,o(j, l, m, o, and qq ), and a numerical example of an equilibrium of the game. ^(36){ }^{36} The precise thresholds between strategies depend on the balance of forces (p)(p) and the costs of war ( TT ). For example, the defender acquiesces when it considers the issue least important, but the cutoff ll between issues that the defender concedes and issues over which it bluffs depends on the balance of forces and the likely costs of war.
Efficacy of a Threat
The goal of a deterrent threat is to make a challenger less likely to attack than it was before hearing the threat. Loosely following Schelling, ^(37){ }^{37} I define the efficacy of a
a. If the defender was not caught bluffing in either of the previous two periods:
Challenger's strategies
Defender’s strategies
Say “won’t Say “will
defend”; don’t defend”; don’t
Say “will
defend defend
defend”; defend
b. If the defender was caught bluffing in either of the previous two periods:
Challenger's strategies
Defender’s strategies
FIGURE 2. Equilibrium strategies
threat as the “value-added” of the defender’s diplomacy. The efficacy of a deterrent threat is the change the defender’s threat causes in the challenger’s beliefs about the defender’s likelihood of fighting. When the defender begins a dispute with a reputation for honesty (top of Figure 2), the challenger begins a dispute believing that the probability that the defender will fight is 1-m1-m. Afterward, it believes that this probability is (1-m)//(1-l)(1-m) /(1-l).
For the equilibrium shown in Figure 2, the defender’s threats have efficacy when the defender has a reputation for honesty. This fact is easily proven :^(38):^{38}
Existence of an interior equilibrium implies that 0 < l,m < 10<l, m<1.
(1-m) < (1-m)//(1-l)(1-m)<(1-m) /(1-l). rarr\rightarrow The defender’s efficacy is positive.
The defender’s threat serves to convince the challenger that the defender is more resolved than the challenger had previously believed.
Similarly, the defender’s threats do not have efficacy when the defender has a reputation for bluffing. The challenger begins a dispute believing that the probability that the defender will fight is
((1-q))/((1-q)+(q-0))\frac{(1-q)}{(1-q)+(q-0)}
or (1-q)(1-q). All defenders try deterrence, and
((1-q))/((1-q)+(q-0))" of these do not defend. "\frac{(1-q)}{(1-q)+(q-0)} \text { of these do not defend. }
The defender’s efficacy is zero. Thus, the game has an equilibrium in which reputations for honesty and for bluffing allow for effective, “cheap” diplomacy.
Effective diplomacy is not an inevitable outcome of international interactions. Though the communications-norm equilibrium is a logical outcome of international interactions, the model has an alternative equilibrium in which states do not acquire reputations and diplomacy is completely ineffective. Thus, the model confirms the logic of an argument made by Ted Hopf and others: Since each dispute involves new issues, there is no logical reason why states’ behavior today must be tied to how they behaved in the past. ^(39){ }^{39} Nevertheless, these two equilibria are not equally plausible from an empirical standpoint, since states do obtain reputations for bluffing.
The model predicts that we will observe bluffs and reputations for bluffing, but few of each. Moreover, states will be more likely to bluff for a short time after they are caught bluffing (though not always); this is why they are less likely to obtain diplomatic success. ^(40){ }^{40} Robert Axelrod and William Zimmerman find little deception in the Soviet press about Soviet foreign policy over a thirty-five-year period. ^(41){ }^{41} Nevertheless, examples of bluffs do exist. In 1962 India pursued a “forward policy,” placing troops forward of Chinese outposts. China repeatedly threatened to respond
with force and backed down. Accordingly, the Indian government dismissed these threats as bluffs, even though China was the stronger power. ^(42){ }^{42} Indian general J. N. Chaudhuri said, “It was a game of Russian roulette, but the highest authorities of India seemed to feel that the one shot in the cylinder was a blank. Unfortunately for them and for the country it was not so. The cylinder was fully loaded.” ^(13){ }^{13} The Chinese attacked in what became the Sino-Indian War.
In the Balkan conflict of 1908-1909, Russia backed down from its initial support for Serbia, leading Serbia to recognize Austria-Hungary’s annexation of BosniaHerzegovina. ^(44){ }^{44} When the Austro-Serbian conflict flared up again in 1912, Russia bluffed again, accepting Albanian independence when it became clear that Germany would support Austria-Hungary. ^(45){ }^{45} Russia’s threats in 1914 then were ineffective. Given the issues, one might have expected Russia’s threats to be more credible in 1914. The issue in 1914 was the invasion of a Slavic state by Austria; based on estimates of Russia’s interests, other states should have believed Russia likely to fight. Not so: In a 1914 letter to the German ambassador to Britain, the German foreign secretary writes, "The more boldness Austria displays, the more strongly we support her, the more likely is Russia to keep quiet. There is certain to be some blustering in St. Petersburg, but at bottom Russia is not now ready to strike. ^(""46 "){ }^{\text {"46 }} Of course, we cannot know if Germany would have been deterrable in 1914 if German leaders had believed the Russian threats. What we do know is that German leaders did not believe the threats and that Russia was not bluffing. Once the Russians became convinced that diplomacy was failing, they mobilized for war. A few days later, Germany mobilized in turn and declared war on Russia. ^(47){ }^{47}
In discussions of reputations for resolve, Jervis questions the idea that backing down is bad for credibility, suggesting instead that states that have backed down will attempt to rebuild their reputations by fighting. ^(48){ }^{48} Since states that are rebuilding their reputations are more likely to fight, the diplomacy of states that retreated recently should be more rather than less credible. As applied to this work, Jervis’s argument (which is directed at reputations for resolve rather than reputations for honesty) suffers from two main weaknesses. First, this behavior probably is not a logical outcome of international interactions. In my model, if states were to possess increased credibility after bluffing, there would be no disincentive to bluff. Without a disincentive to bluff, states would bluff often and diplomacy never would be effective. Second, the empirical record does not support the conjecture that states obtain a surge in credibility after bluffing. To the contrary, like China and Russia in
the cases just discussed, states that have been caught bluffing obtain reputations for bluffing and suffer losses of credibility.
Situational Reputations
Scholars usually argue that reputations are dispositional: They stem from underlying differences among people, firms, or states. ^(49){ }^{49} For example, David M. Kreps and Robert Wilson argue that monopolists may be strong or weak, and that they wish to develop reputations for strength in order to convince upstart firms not to enter the market. ^(50){ }^{50} Schelling suggests that states may be resolute or irresolute (and that resolve is at least partly an enduring characteristic), and that they wish to acquire reputations for resolve in order to increase their credibility in international conflict. ^(51){ }^{51}
In contrast, states in my model have no permanent differences in disposition. This difference reflects my belief that the crucial information-how much the state values the disputed issue-varies from one dispute to the next. Whether or not a state has the “will to fight” depends on what the issues are and so must be communicated anew through the use of diplomacy.
Since, by assumption, there are no enduring dispositions, the reputations that emerge in this model are situational. Like a dispositional reputation, a situational reputation is an assessment-based on past, observed behavior-that a state is likely to behave in a certain way in the future. Defenders lie or tell the truth depending on the situation they are in, and they acquire reputations based on this behavior. Since a defender that is caught bluffing is actually more likely to lie in the near future, it is rational to assign that defender a reputation for dishonesty. While these situational reputations could be considered a modeling simplification, they also may be an interesting real-world phenomenon.
In their minds, leaders may attribute reputations for bluffing to disposition, thinking this state tends to lie. Such an error would be in keeping with my model; as long as leaders are less likely to believe the bluffer in its next interaction, the communications norm will work. Such an attribution error also would be consistent with portions of psychological theory, which argues that persons overattribute undesirable behavior to disposition. ^(52)A{ }^{52} \mathrm{~A} detailed comparison of the beliefs in my model with those in psychological theory is not explored here, and a precise match is unlikely to occur. However, this consistency hints at similarities between rational choice and psychological approaches to decision making.
Diplomacy, Commitment, and War
I suggested at the beginning of this article that diplomacy allows states to realize common interests. To pursue this line of reasoning, I now engage in a thought experiment: I compare the real world, in which states do communicate, to a hypothetical world in which communication is impossible. I do so by comparing two equilibria: the partially communicative equilibrium discussed earlier (which represents the real world) and an equilibrium in which states never can communicate (which represents the hypothetical world without communication). In the noncommunicative equilibrium, states play the strategies in the bottom half of Figure 2 forever rather than alternating between the two sets of strategies.
Two results related to states’ well-being stem from the fact that credibility allows states to use diplomacy as a form of commitment. Commitment is a double-edged sword. The defender is less likely to suffer an attack when it can commit itself than when it cannot. However, for its diplomacy to be effective, the defender must be willing to follow through. ^(53){ }^{53} Thus, the defender gets more of what it wants when it can communicate. However, war can be more common with communication than without. ^(54){ }^{54}
For reasons of tractability, I examine a situation in which the challenger cannot communicate. In an analogous equilibrium with bilateral communication, I conjecture that the logic of the equilibrium would carry over. The challenger, too, would obtain issues that it valued more over time, on average, with the help of communication. Thus, states would attain a “trade” of issues over time as suggested at the beginning of the article, conceding less important issues and keeping or acquiring more important ones.
The Korean War Revisited
This article began with a reference to China’s failed attempt to deter the United States from crossing the thirty-eighth parallel during the Korean War. Many U.S. leaders believed that a fight over Korea was not in China’s best interest. ^(55){ }^{55} Yet, as I noted earlier, Chinese leaders stated flatly that China would enter the war if U.S. troops crossed the parallel, and U.S. leaders dismissed the Chinese threats as bluffs.
Scholars and policymakers have proposed many reasons for the communication failure. These include the timing of the threats prior to a crucial UN vote, the fact that some of the threats were relayed through the mistrusted Indian ambassador K. M. Panikkar, ^(56){ }^{56} and “groupthink” on the part of U.S. leaders. ^(57){ }^{57}
These explanations are unsatisfying for a variety of reasons. The choice of Panikkar as a messenger is a poor explanation because many of the threats were not made by Panikkar; they were issued directly by Chinese government officials or published in the official press. For example, on 22 September 1950 China admitted sending aid to the North Koreans and threatened to send more. A Ministry of Foreign Affairs spokesman said that China “will always stand on the side of the Korean people.” ^(58){ }^{58} The timing of the threats is an equally poor explanation for U.S. officials’ disbelief; the warnings continued after the vote in question, and U.S. leaders still considered them to be bluffs.
Groupthink is an insufficient explanation because President Truman, Secretary of State Acheson, and others had major disagreements with General MacArthur. Janis argues, "The mutual support for risk-taking, it seems to me, was part of a more general pattern of concurrence-seeking behavior, which also fosters uncritical acceptance of stereotypes of out-groups and a sense of unanimity about the wisdom and morality of past decisions. ^(59){ }^{59} Yet this case involves much behavior that cannot be explained as concurrence-seeking: Truman and others were notably and consciously unhappy with many of MacArthur’s views, statements, and actions over the course of the war, particularly with his desire to involve the Taiwanese in the Korean conflict. ^(60){ }^{60} Rather than groupthink in this crisis, there was substantial disagreement-but almost no disagreement over whether or not the Chinese were bluffing. ^(61){ }^{61}
Some scholars argue that MacArthur was eager to proceed into North Korea regardless of whether he believed China would carry out its threats and that Truman ultimately agreed with his view. ^(62){ }^{62} That debate is interesting, but the relevant question here is whether MacArthur and other top leaders believed China’s threats, not what MacArthur or the United States would have done had they believed them. At his Wake Island conference with Truman, MacArthur stated that he did not believe China would enter the war. ^(63){ }^{63} Part-way through the war, MacArthur was relieved of his command and Congress held an unusual set of hearings into the military situation in the Far East and into the circumstances surrounding his relief. ^(64){ }^{64} At these hearings, MacArthur mentioned a November CIA report that "said that they felt there was little chance of any major intervention on the part of the Chinese forces. ^(165){ }^{165} In fact, it is remarkable that in an administration replete with power struggles over the conduct of the war, the president, the secretary of state, members
of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, and MacArthur all were aware of the Chinese threats and to various degrees dismissed them as bluffs. ^(66){ }^{66} Though they were eager to blame each other for the conduct of the war, none of these leaders argued that the others did believe the Chinese threats. One reason for MacArthur’s disbelief was that he considered China’s military capabilities inferior. This fact does not, however, explain other leaders’ dismissal of the threats as bluffs. Even the Joint Chiefs of Staff believed that the Chinese had sufficient capabilities to enter the war if they wanted to do so. ^(67){ }^{67} The question thus remains: Why did so many U.S. leaders disbelieve the threats?
A final explanation is that China had acquired a reputation for bluffing through a series of bluffs over Taiwan. ^(68){ }^{68} The model of diplomacy I develop here helps to shed light on China’s failed communication by explaining when and why states acquire reputations for bluffing and the negative consequences of such a reputation for a state’s diplomacy. In the period before the war and in its early months, China was almost, though not quite, ready to fight over Taiwan. China’s leaders went so far as to make invasion plans but did not follow through. ^(69){ }^{69} China threatened to enter the Korean War in the context of its having made a series of unfulfilled threats to fight over Taiwan. For example, early in the summer of 1950, Mao stated that the Chinese would invade Taiwan by September, but they did not do so. ^(70){ }^{70} Many of China’s threats over Korea came in September and October 1950, just after this particular threat to invade Taiwan had been revealed as bluff. ^(71){ }^{71} China’s history of bluffing contributed to the widespread belief in the United States that China’s threats to intervene in the Korean War were bluffs.
Why was China prepared to fight over Korea but not quite prepared to invade Taiwan in 1950?One reason is that Chinese leaders worried that U.S. forces would march straight through North Korea into China. For example, Mao cabled Chou En-lai that "not to have intervened . . . would have meant that ‘the reactionaries at home and abroad would be swollen with arrogance when the enemy troops press on toward the Yalu River [the border between North Korea and China].’ „72
Would China’s threats over Korea have been more successful had it not threatened Taiwan? Any answer to this question is speculative. Nevertheless, prior to these conflicts, U.S. leaders seem to have believed that China was more likely to
fight over Taiwan than over Korea. ^(73){ }^{73} If, in the early 1950s, China had said it was willing to let Taiwan live in peace, this news would have come as a surprise to the United States. If China soon thereafter had said it was unwilling to tolerate U.S. troops in North Korea, U.S. leaders might well have concluded that preventing a U.S. occupation of North Korea was quite important to the Chinese.
Conclusion 结论
In this article I demonstrate the roles of honesty and reputation in crisis bargaining. I argue that diplomacy works because it is beneficial, and states have an incentive to preserve their ability to use it. Using diplomacy, states communicate information about which issues they consider particularly important and thus increase their chances of prevailing when these issues are at stake. The flip side is that states must concede those issues they consider less crucial; by doing so, they maintain credibility for disputes in which they consider the stakes higher.
This analysis has several implications for understanding crisis behavior and communication. First, the work fills a gap in theories of crisis behavior by explaining why cheap talk can change an adversary’s mind about a state’s resolve. I do not argue that costly signals are meaningless; states’ choices to use cheap talk or costly signals remains an important subject for future research. One conjecture is that a state will turn to costly signals when the currency of cheap talk has been devalued by bluffing and the state considers the issue exceptionally importantRussia at the beginning of World War I might be an example. Of course, if it were always possible to use costly signaling to avoid the repercussions of bluffing, then cheap talk would never be credible.
Second, the model has novel, testable implications about states’ behavior in international disputes. Here, I develop one central implication: As was the case for China in the Korean War, a state’s deterrence success is less likely to be effective and the state is less likely to attain its goals when it has a reputation for bluffing; it is more likely to succeed when it has a reputation for honesty. This hypothesis is testable because the concept of reputations incorporated in this model can be readily operationalized. If a state acquiesced or fought a war recently, it currently has a reputation for honesty; otherwise, it has a reputation for bluffing. Of course, the model is based on a simplifying assumption that a state knows nothing about its opponent’s value for the issues at the beginning of a new international dispute. In the real world, I would expect that a priori beliefs about the importance of a dispute to an adversary would also affect the probability of deterrence success. The reputations hypothesis in this article differs from that of deterrence theory: The model I propose suggests that acquiescing in one dispute leads to a reputation for
honesty, so acquiescing is positively associated with success in the next dispute; deterrence theory suggests that acquiescing in one dispute leads to a reputation for lacking resolve, so it is negatively associated with success in the next dispute. The reputations hypothesis also is contrary to audience-cost models, which suggest no association between a state’s recent behavior and the outcome of the current dispute. ^(74){ }^{74}
As mentioned earlier, some deterrence theorists have questioned the idea that reputations for resolve generalize. For example, Paul Huth argues that states might pay attention only to their regional neighbors or to their partners in enduring rivalries, ignoring the outcomes of unrelated disputes. ^(75){ }^{75} This same question arises with reputations for honesty. The results presented here hold even if we consider the challenger and the defender always to be the same two states interacting over time. Nevertheless, the question of when states assign reputations is an important one, and the answer affects the precise implications of the model. If states pay attention to all disputes (as in an informal version of the Law Merchant ^(76){ }^{76} ), then whether or not a state is caught bluffing in the current dispute affects its next interaction, regardless of the adversary. If states ignore disputes outside of their regions, then a reputation affects a state’s next dispute in its region. Since either answer is logically possible, the question can best be addressed empirically. This empirical work is another topic for future research.
Third, encouraged by Robert Putnam’s well-known study, a growing number of international relations scholars have turned their attention to domestic influences on foreign policy. ^(77){ }^{77} While this research program is valuable, my analysis here sounds a warning note about the dangers of neglecting systemic factors. I demonstrate formally that domestic audiences are unnecessary for effective signaling. Moreover, I show that crisis bargaining models that assume domestic audiences punish leaders who back down are assuming irrational behavior on the part of domestic publics. While bluffing is rare, it nevertheless can be the best policy. ^(78){ }^{78} Backing down is always best for a state that is caught bluffing; if a state considered the issue important enough to be worth a fight, it would not be bluffing. Thus, a rational domestic audience should not punish a leader for backing down, as the audiencecost literature assumes it will. The different models have different implications: The audience-cost literature suggests a correlation between regime type and deterrence
success, whereas the model I propose suggests that democracies and autocracies should be equally able to use diplomacy and equally likely to deter attacks. ^(79){ }^{79}
Fourth, my analysis provides an example of the benefits of the theory of infinitely repeated games as a tool for understanding international relations. Most international relationships are ongoing. Without repeated games, scholars must make many more assumptions about the ways in which the past and the future influence present choices. While such simplifications often yield valuable insights, they also distort the effects of the past and the future.
Finally, although this work directly concerns only diplomacy, it suggests ways to understand communication more generally. Like the “cheap talk” literature in economics, I argue that common interests help actors communicate. In most human interactions, the ability to communicate has significant value. Precisely because dishonesty places the ability to communicate in the future at risk and all parties understand this, persons and states can convey information through the use of language.
Appendix
Technical Characterization of the Equilibrium
The text describes an equilibrium of the game in which the defender’s threats convey information to the challenger. The parameters in Figure 2 can be considered thresholds; for instance, a challenger with a value above the threshold oo finds it optimal to attack in time tt if the defender was caught bluffing in time t-1t-1 or t-2t-2. Choosing thresholds amounts to choosing strategies. Thus, formally characterizing the equilibrium consists of finding equations for the thresholds such that the thresholds constitute optimal solutions to the states’ maximization problems.
The equilibrium described here is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium, which is an extension of the Nash equilibrium concept to games of incomplete information. At every information set, no state can wish to deviate from its prescribed equilibrium strategy, given the beliefs and strategies of the other states. In addition, beliefs must, if possible, be updated according to Bayes’s rule.
The beliefs of players off the equilibrium path are as follows. Since a player gets a new type at the beginning of each interaction, a player beginning a new interaction believes that the other player is equally likely to be of any type at that point in time, even if the player’s previous actions have been off the equilibrium path. Within an interaction, the only off-path beliefs that could affect play are the beliefs of a challenger when the defender is being ignored (punished). The equilibrium I examine specifies that a defender that is being ignored always says that it will defend the issues. If the challenger observes a deviation (the defender saying that it will not defend), the challenger’s off-path beliefs are that the straying defender is equally likely to have any value for the issues. In this event, the challenger’s strategies after
a discovered bluff are not tied to the defender’s words; after observing this deviation, challengers with issue values below oo refrain from attack and those with values above oo attack. Thus, the defender weakly prefers its equilibrium strategy.
Equilibrium Analysis
I begin by using factorization to write the defender’s expected payoffs from time tt onward for arbitrary values of the thresholds j,l,m,oj, l, m, o, and q*^(80)q \cdot{ }^{80} Factorization is the Bellman principle applied to a game-theoretic model. After any tt-period history, any equilibrium must specify a successor equilibrium. An equilibrium can be factorized into the strategies it specifies for the current period and the strategies it specifies from tomorrow onward. Thus, verifying that a player does not wish to deviate from the equilibrium strategies requires checking that it is not worthwhile to deviate once (today), given that the players play their equilibrium strategies from tomorrow onward. In the equilibrium described here, one must keep in mind that the successor strategies depend on today’s play and that there are thus two different continuation values.
In particular, the defender’s expected payoff from tt onward depends on whether the defender was or was not caught bluffing in time t-1t-1 or t-2t-2. Call the discount factor delta\delta, the total expected payoff from tt onward for the defender who was not caught bluffing in time t-1t-1 or t-2t-2, " w1w 1," and the total expected payoff from tt onward for the defender who was caught bluffing in time t-1t-1, " w2w 2." There is a separate expected payoff from tt onward for a defender who was caught bluffing in time t-2t-2.
The threshold for a defender who was caught bluffing in time t-2t-2 is just qq (the same as for a defender who was caught bluffing in time t-1t-1 ), because the defender’s choice of strategy in either of these situations does not influence its continuation value. Similarly, the challenger’s threshold when the defender was caught bluffing in time t-2t-2 is oo.
Referring to Figure 2 for the meaning of the thresholds and the associated equilibrium strategies, the expected payoffs can be written as follows: